"Who Wants to Die for Art!?!": Reflections on a Meta-Film Sub-Genre: Part I
ππ°π±π¦: Transcendence and Self-Incrimination through the Art of Crime
Click here to read the Introduction to this series
Ropeβs narrative begins with the strangulation of a young man named David Kentley (Dick Hogan) by two of his prep school classmates, Brandon Shaw (John Dall) and Phillip Morgan (Farley Granger). Brandon is enlivened by the murder, but Phillip expresses remorse for his role in the grisly deed, and this difference in the killersβ reactions mirrors their βalpha-betaβ relationship, which is coded as gay (Brandon and Phillip are based on the notorious real-life lovers Nathan Freudenthal Leopold Jr. and Richard Albert Loeb, who in 1924 abducted and killed a fourteen-year-old for the same reasons Brandon and Phillip kill their victim.) Before guests (including Davidβs father and girlfriend) arrive to the party they host in their Manhattan apartment, Brandon and Phillip conceal the corpse in a wooden chest and discuss their motivation for killing David: the sheer thrill of doing so.
This βfor the sake of itβ ethos is connected in Arthur LaurentsβsΒ script (as adapted from Patrick Hamiltonβs play; Hume Cronyn wrote the filmβs story treatment) to the artistβs ability to aestheticize and ennoble reality, including its ugliest elements. At various points throughout the film, Brandon makes this connection explicit: βIβve always wished for more artistic talent. Well, murder can be an art, too. The power to kill can be just as satisfying as the power to create,β andΒ β[The partyβs] the finishing touch to our work. Itβs more. Itβs the signature of the artists,β and so on. Itβs worth noting that while Brandon wishes βfor more artistic talent,β a wish that he transforms into a reality through his orchestration of βthe perfect murder,β Phillip is an actual artist, a piano player and actor β Phillipβs ability to express himself creatively might account for his disgust at, and guilt for, having participated in Brandonβs act of destruction, the homicidal medium through which he expresses himself.
Brandonβs warped aestheticism is in turn associated with an intellectual, creative, and moral superiority he believes people like himself and Phillip possess over and above the βordinary average man,β βthe inferior man,β for whom βgood and evil, right and wrong were inventedβ¦because he needs them.β According to this philosophy β extremely similar to that of Friedrich Nietzsche, whom another character directly references β Brandon and Phillipβs superiority bestows upon them the right to exercise brutal power over people like David because βthe Davids of this world merely occupy space, which is why he was the perfect victim for the perfect murder.β
At the party, Brandonβs former prep school housemaster, cultural studies author Rupert Cadell (James Stewart), expresses agreement with Brandonβs philosophical views and also likens murder to an art. Indeed, Brandon tells Phillip that heβs invited Rupert to the party because Rupert is the only person who would not only understand but also approve of Davidβs murder. Along with Phillipβs increasingly agitated behavior, Brandon drops enough hints about the killing β often through puns, double-entendres and veiled allusions, verbal corollaries of the βgameβ he plays in hiding Davidβs corpse among his party guests β to arouse the writerβs suspicions that something is amiss, and in this way Brandon fosters the audience needed for his βartisticβ crime to be sufficiently appreciated as a βmasterpiece.β
Eventually Rupert uncovers the murder and discovers Davidβs corpse, and at filmβs climax he denounces Brandon, Phillip, and his own amoral philosophical pretensions:
βTonight youβve made me ashamed of every concept I ever had of superior or inferior beings. But I thank you for that shame, because now I know that we are each of us a separate human being, Brandon. With the right to live and work and think as individuals, but with an obligation to the society we live in. By what right do you dare to say that thereβs a superior few to which you belong? By what right did you decide that that boy in there was inferior and could be killed? Did you think you were God, Brandon? Is that what you thought when you choked the life out of him? Is that what you thought when you served food from his grave?! I don't know who you are but I know what you've done. You've murdered! You choked the life out of a fellow human being who could live and love as you never could, and never will again!β
On the surface,Β RopeΒ functions as a clever βhowcatchem?β (as opposed to a βwhodunnit?β) as well as a clear-cut denunciation of moral relativism by way of Hitchcockβs supreme proficiency in the suspense thriller genre. But on a deeper level, Rope β like so many of Hitchcockβs best works β is a chilling implication and self-implication of this very aestheticization. Thatβs because the filmβs driving aesthetic element is the βprogrammatic perfectionβ (to use literary critic and film scholar D.A. Millerβs description of Ropeβs perceived visual purity) of a single, unbroken shot (114).
The operative word here is βperceivedβ since the actual construction of RopeΒ contains, after its title sequence, what only appears to be an unbroken shot that runs for approximately 78 minutes. ThisΒ unbroken shot is really ten shots of various durations that were edited seamlessly so as to seem continuous, but even this illusionary βsingle, unbroken takeβ contains four unconcealed and typically unacknowledged cuts. (These cuts occur at the end of each of Ropeβs four reels so as to coincide with projection changeovers.) So seamlessly executed is the βsingle, unbroken take,β and so ensconced in cinematic legend is that takeβs construction and appearance, that only until very recently did I notice the four unconcealed edits contained therein β and only after I was informed of them.
But even if only an artistic βidealβ (FranΓ§ois Truffaut called Rope the realization of a directorβs βdream of linking all of a filmβs components into a single, continuous actionβ), the βsingle, unbroken shotβ calls blatant and unmistakable attention to Rope as art, and an artificial construction (184). Ironically so, for even though it unfolds in a more βlifelikeβ fashion than almost all other Hollywood films (one can argue that we visually experience life as a single, unbroken shot), Rope stands conspicuously apart from these films due to the conventionalized βlifelikenessβ they achieve through classical continuity editing.1
In his famous series of interviews with Truffaut, Hitchcock dismissed the experimental construction of RopeΒ as pointless: for all of its long-take virtuosity, the Master claimed, the film nonetheless adheres to a classical sequence of camera positions and angles β long shots to orient the audience as to the spatial parameters of the setting and the charactersβ movement within it, closer shots to emphasize important facial expressions or details within the setting, etc. β and so the βsingle, unbroken shotβ of which Rope is mainly composed proves technically impressive but ultimately ornamental (180). Yet Hitchcock failed to give himself proper credit, since Ropeβs eschewal of classical continuity editingβs conventionalized βinvisibilityβ (that is, the inconspicuous transitions among separate shots) encourages an unusual experience in which viewer awareness of the cameraβs spatial relationship to characters and other elements of mise-en-scΓ¨ne is not only activated but intensely heightened.
By shooting Rope largely through the βsingle, unbroken shot,β Hitchcock primes his audience to view his film in far less βrealisticβ terms than an audience would almost all other films, and thus he foregrounds his creation as a work of art and not as a verisimilar representation of reality. The irony that the βsingle, unbroken shotβ masks its four unconcealed cuts β at least for most viewers, including this one β better than would a conventionally constructed and edited film speaks to Ropeβs tense relationship with immersive spectacle. Most films contain artificial elements that unintentionally (and sometimes intentionally) distance the viewer from complete immersion in spectacle, but not by employing the kind of extreme oscillations Hitchcock employs to push the viewer into and pull the viewer out from the fictional drama. In Rope, the βlifelikenessβ of the βsingle, unbroken shotβ can evoke the absorbing quality of a dream, but it can also evoke the contrived nature of a self-consciously performed stage play.
In this way, the very construction ofΒ Rope parallels Brandon and Phillipβs motivation for committing murder β something gratuitous2 that enhances reality, or at least enhances oneβs relationship to it β and so the audienceβs motivation for watching Rope, and perhaps the cinema as a whole,Β is brought into the harsh light of day: we watch movies to aesthetically βredeemβ subjects we find βinferiorβ and to aesthetically βenlivenβ circumstances and situations we consider βordinary.β (A proposed experiment: a re-edit of Ropeβs party sequence so that it loses a few secretive side-conversations between Brandon and Phillip and is no longer preceded by the murder sequence nor followed by the climactic confrontation between Rupert and the killers. Would the party be at all interesting without an audienceβs knowledge that a corpse was hidden amid the partygoers?)
Hitchcock confronts the audience with its desire for transcendence through art, a desire that mirrors the killersβ desire for transcendence through a creatively orchestrated murder and its concealment. Hitchcock suggests that the difference in the motivation of βthrill-killersβ and the motivation of artists and art consumers may lie more in degree than in kind: an underlying dissatisfaction with the βordinaryβ and even βinferiorβ aspects of reality that drive people to seek βsomething moreβ motivates both art and murder, even, or especially if, that βsomething moreβ has no practical or socially redeeming purpose. In this sense, the coded gay relationship between Brandon and Phillip (and the coded or not-so-coded queerness of so many killers in Hitchcockβs films, from Joseph Cottenβs Uncle Charlie in Shadow of a Doubt [1943] to Anthony Perkinsβs Norman Bates in Psycho [1960]) reinforces Ropeβs theme, since Brandon and Phillipβs sexuality is βexcessiveβ and βnon-productiveβ (according to the values of mainstream American society) in the way of so much βart for artβs sake.β3
One can reasonably argue that creating or enjoying art is not nearly the same as ending the life of a human being β that art is almost always victimless, whereas murder by definition involves the dispatching of a victim. But this is where Rope complicates matters with the character of Rupert. If Brandon and Phillip make crime their art, then the audience for whom they intend to entertain and impress is Rupert, the teacher who imparted to his former charges the ideas of murder-as-art and murder-as-the-privilege-of-the-superior-few. Between the killers and Rupert exists a feedback loop predicated on the desire for transcendence over the practical or βpositiveβ applications of art as well as the limitations of society through transgressive acts that prove oneβs intellectual, creative, and, thereby, moral superiority. But though Rupert inspires Brandon and Phillip, the teacher differs from his pupils in sincerity. Rupert half-jokingly espouses his ideas while his students turn these ideas into reality by bringing them to their logical, horrific conclusion. As Thomas M. Bauso points out, Rupertβs facetiousness provides the core means through which Hitchcock aligns the sympathies of the audience with those of the character: βFor the audience can more easily be teased into identifying with the character and thus can be entrapped by that identification at the end of the film, when the deadly consequences of Cadellβs cavalier toying with ideas are fully brought home to him, and the space between his play-acting and his pupilsβ acting-out of his fantasy is dramatically closedβ (234).
Unlike most Hitchcock films in which spectator identification with characters is achieved through point-of-view editing, Rope remains βoutsideβ of its characters β the film never employs point-of-view editing, and so the audience never perceives and experiences events through the charactersβ eyes. Rupert functions as Ropeβs audience-surrogate, though through a strategy diametrically opposed to Hitchcockβs usual methods. Rather than gradually βembeddingβ the viewer into or βaligningβ the audience with Rupertβs subjectivity through point-of-view editing, Rope has Rupert assume the viewerβs omniscient vantage point β as fostered by the roving movement of the βsingle, unbroken shotβ β as he gradually catches up with the audienceβs knowledge of events and discovers the murder. Rupertβs discovery, however, leads to disillusionment as well as mastery: In denouncing Brandon and Phillip, Rupert distances himself from their crime, but also implicates himself in having shared the ideology that motivated them to commit it.
Rupertβs subjectivity becomes fully meshed with both the killersβ and the audienceβs subjectivity, particularly in one of the filmβs most ingenious sequences, a pseudo-point-of-view within the βsingle, unbroken shotβ that suggests what Rupert would have seen or how he would have navigated within Brandon and Phillipβs apartment if he himself were to have killed David. No characters are in frame during this sequence, and so Rupertβs step-by-step narration of the imaginary murder, which verbally recreates the actual murder committed by Brandon and Phillip, provides the sequenceβs only βactionβ β the audience is thus encouraged to visualize the events that led up to Davidβs murder in the same manner that Rupert imagines and describes them. Beyond that, Rupertβs plan for entrapping the murderers involves a creative indulgence that replicates that of the killers. Rather than simply report to the police his suspicion of Davidβs murder (a suspicion founded on more than just Brandonβs hints and Phillipβs bizarre behavior, since Rupert discovers telltale evidence of the murder via Davidβs hat, which Brandon and Phillip foolishly leave in their hallway closet), Rupert cleverly goads the killers into a confession with verbal taunts, feints, and allusions. Rupertβs interest in artistic βplayβ over and above pragmatic, socially conscious responsibility is recognized and called out by Phillip when he likens Rupertβs ploys to his and Brandonβs own propensity to delight in sick βgamesβ: βCat and mouse,Β cat and mouse! But which is the cat and which is the mouse?β
Thomas Hemmeter points out that Rupertβs favoring of βplayβ over responsibility enters into the very logic β or illogic β he uses to philosophically separate himself from Brandon and Phillip (256). Rupertβs climactic denunciation of the killers is also an unintentional admission that he never attached genuine meaning to his words concerning murder-as-art and murder-as-the-privilege-of-the-superior-few, and so, in effect, he was just βplayingβ with language and βtoyingβ with ideas:
βBut youβve given my words a meaning that I never dreamed of! And youβve tried to twist them into a cold, logical excuse for your ugly murder! Well, they never were that, Brandon, and you canβt make them that. There must have been something deep inside you from the very start that let you do this thing, but thereβs always been something deep inside me that would never let me do it β and would never let me be a party to it now.β
Hemmeter sees Rupert as a βstructuralistβ (as opposed to Brandonβs βdeconstructionistβ) who feebly attempts to control ideological play by anchoring the explosive potentialities of his irresponsible language with a meaning that exists outside language itself, a mysterious and never-defined βsomething deep inside meβ that is moral and upright as opposed to the βsomething deep insideβ Brandon that took from Rupertβs words βa cold, logical excuse for [his] ugly murderβ (257-261). Rupertβs attempt to divorce himself from Brandonβs artistic playfulness itself indulges in an artistic play with words, and this circularity is perhaps one of the reasons Rupert feels βshameβ for having inspired the murderers. It is not only that Rupert believed the same ideas that led to the murder of David, but that he participates, both as an audience member and as an artist, in the kind of irresponsible and purposeless creativity that animates his mentees.
As Hemmeter shows, Rupertβs failure to convincingly distance his values from Brandon and Phillipβs values mirrors the repeated dead-ends commentators have encountered when attempting to reconcile Ropeβs formal conceit with its purported meaning (253-254). Historically, critics have either dismissed the film as indulging in an experimentation that outstrips its meaning, and in so doing they have refused to acknowledge the ways in which Ropeβs construction is integral to the communication of that meaning; or else critics have recuperated Ropeβs integrity as a meaningful narrative by divorcing it from the filmβs experimentation, and in so doing they have reduced Ropeβs ideas and implications to the moralistically simplistic.
The overall result of the strategies that Hitchcock uses to identify the audience with both the killers and Rupert, as well as the strategies he uses to identify Rupert with the killers, is that Ropeβs audience becomes implicated in sharing the three major charactersβ desire for transgression in pursuit of the Real, that βsomething moreβ that art promises but that crime delivers. Bauso explains:
βNo moment in the film more clearly invites the audienceβs compassion for Rupertβs tragic insight [as Rupertβs discovery of Davidβs corpse], but the supreme irony of this sympathy resides in the parallel between the audienceβs identification with Rupert and its own implication in his crime. For he is inarguably, though indirectly, guilty of Davidβs murder, and so his shallow speech of self-justification at the end goes beyond simple hypocrisy or obtuseness and enters a transcendent realm of the absurd. To laugh at Rupertβs ludicrous rationalizing is, for the audience, to laugh at itself (237).β
Rope encourages dark, self-incriminating laughter not by mocking its audienceβs temporary abandonment of democratic values and Judeo-Christian morality in identifying with the killers and their unwitting role model β a frivolous objective in any case, since the vast majority of Ropeβs viewers donβt stand in danger of imposing a violent Nietzschean βwill to powerβ over others β but instead by uncovering the anti-social impulses at the heart of artistic practice and appreciation. Just as Brandon and Phillip might never have murdered David if they hadnβt conceived of their act as a work of art that would be applauded by someone sharing their desire to transcend βordinary valuesβ through the transgression of written and unwritten law, so might Hitchcock have never directed Rope if he hadnβt been aware that audiences desire to transcend the βordinaryβ through the transgressions of art.
Rope is no mere βhaving its caking and eating it, tooβ film β a zero-sum exercise that scolds an audience for enjoying the very entertainment it provides. Instead, with Rope Hitchcock examines his and his audienceβs participatory roles in a centuries-old circuit of art production and reception. Frequently instigating that circuit, Hitchcock suggests, are amoral β if not immoral β desires entirely at odds with the oft-stated positive motivations of artistic practice: the creation of beauty, the revelation of truth, the imparting of ethics. Perhaps the ultimate irony of the thoroughly ironic Rope is that even while possessing these positive motivations the film never allows them to fully counterbalance or βredeemβ the ideological and aesthetic transgressions that propel its narrative. Its beauty consists of gratuitous and self-conscious artifice, its revelation exposes the selfish, destructive philosophical underpinnings of over-developed intelligence and creativity, and its ethical instruction incriminates the audience rather than solely condemning an evil βotherβ from whom the audience can maintain a safe moral distance.
Above all, Hitchcock implies with Rope that his work as an artist is fueled by a mischievous, gleeful manipulation only a stoneβs throw from his villainous charactersβ full-fledged sadism, and that β because art so often involves indulgence in mischievous and manipulative βfree playβ β the artistβs work as a whole is a sort of glorified criminality, an excursion into transgression with only the flimsiest of socially-approved justifications.
Works Cited
Bauso, Thomas M., βRope: Hitchcockβs Unkindest Cut,β Hitchcockβs Rereleased Films: From Rope to Vertigo, Ed. Walter Raubicheck and Walter Srebnick, Detriot: Wayne State University Press, 1991, Print, 226-239.
Hemmeter, Thomas, βTwisted Writing: Rope as an Experimental Film,β Hitchcockβs Rereleased Films: From Rope to Vertigo, Ed. Walter Raubicheck and Walter Srebnick, Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1991, Print, 253-265.
Miller, D.A., βAnal Rope,β Representations, No. 32 (Autumn 1990), University of California Press, Print, 114-133.
Truffaut, François, Hitchcock, Trans. Helen G. Scott, New York: Touchstone, 1985, Revised Edition, Print.
Another major difference between Rope and most other Hollywood films is that the former almost entirely eschews soundtrack music. A theme plays over the opening credits β up to the last moments of the introductory establishing shot β and the closing credits, but otherwise Rope unfolds without an extra-diegetic musical score or musical cues, which are typically employed to immerse audiences in a movieβs visual action: here again, Hitchcock chooses to keep his audience at a remove from what they watch. Furthermore, at a couple of points Phillip performs the filmβs theme on a piano. One of these performances occurs at the very end of the film, just prior to the closing credits, as if Phillipβs performance was supposed to lead into the theme as it plays in extra-diegetic form over the credits. These instances, in which the extra-diegetic musical theme is taken up within the diegesis, lend to RopeΒ an additional layer of meta-cinematic artifice. Itβs also worth mentioning that Rope was Hitchcockβs first color film. As with the 78-minute βsingle, unbroken shotβ and the relative lack of extra-diegetic soundtrack music, color in Rope initially appears to be a lifelike and realistic cinematic element β at least in comparison to black-and-white film stock β but Hitchcock uses it for increasingly expressionistic and borderline-hallucinatory effect, especially toward the end of the film when a glowing neon sign outside Brandon and Phillipβs apartment bathes the characters in pulsating flashes of red.
The βgratuitousβ character of Ropeβs construction is evident in the logistical difficulties of shooting the film. These difficulties reached an apex when Hitchcock noticed a color error in the dailies that necessitated the complete re-shooting of the filmβs last five reels. Needless to say, had Hitchcock shot the film conventionally such an error would not have produced so much wasted time and celluloid (Truffaut 181).
Much has been written about Hitchcockβs depiction of coded queer characters, and it is, admittedly, much more complex and nuanced than the brief treatment I afford the issue in this essay. For more on the topic see Theodore Priceβs Hitchcock and Homosexuality: His 50-Year Obsession with Jack the Ripper and the Superbitch Prostitute: A Psychoanalytic View (Scarecrow Press, 1992) as well as the chapter βThe Murderous Gays: Hitchcockβs Homophobiaβ from Robin Woodβs Hitchcockβs Films Revisited (Columbia University Press, 2002).